Is it respectable to be agnostic about
the existence of God, or is it simply a form of cowardice? The agnostic
suspends belief on the question of God's existence because neither theists nor
atheists can prove their claims beyond a reasonable doubt. Not even our
contemporary atheists claim to prove, deductively, that God does not exist.
However, sensible atheists try to show that God's existence is so unliksely
that we have no rational warrant for
belief in God. The key, here, is to decide how important it is to have
rational grounds for believing in God. If one agrees with a logically minded
philosopher like Bertram Russell, then we ought to believe only that for which
we have good reasons. Not having good reasons for believing in something will
count against believing in it. Traditionally, philosophers commit themselves to
finding the best reasons for their beliefs.
The question of God's existence is a
metaphysical one, and this is part of the problem. Metaphysical questions do
not find firm answers in the history of philosophy. Though individuals may
stand firm until they die, the arguments go on. Critics have complained that
there is no apparent progress in metaphysics. Philosophers are still arguing
about God, and the same old arguments go round and round under different
reformulations. Nevertheless, we can explain this apparent lack of progress by
noting that such is the nature of metaphysical debate. Each position has its
own set of assumptions and convictions,
and proponents believe that they can accommodate all of them within one
metaphysical view or another. The trouble is that two clashing metaphysical
views cannot both be true, yet each asserts the truth of its own position. Fighting ensues, but
victory is temporary and rhetorical. Now one side has the upper hand, now the
other.
However, there is no reason to despair
over this state of affairs. Each side in a metaphysical debate is learning from
its opponent just what its own position is. By learning to defend and to
attack, each side gains a depth of understanding about its own view and that of
the opponent, even while realizing that ultimate agreement is unlikely, given
their differing assumptions and commitments. This does not render the
conversation pointless. It shows us that the element of choice is paramount in
shaping metaphysical convictions. Nothing determines one's ultimate posture
toward the universe but oneself. Theists choose to believe in God. Atheists do
not. The former believes in supernatural powers and causes, the latter believes
that everything we can understand has a natural explanation. An agnostic feels
that the leap of faith into theism or atheism is without foundation and thus,
like a skeptic, suspends belief.
The stand of not knowing whether God
exists is certainly a logically possible position. If one cannot prove the
existence or nonexistence of God, then agnosticism is also intellectually
respectable, and, perhaps, theoretically unavoidable. However, is it morally or
ethically respectable? Perhaps the courageous thing to do is to assert a
consistent atheism as the most likely theory, given what we know of ourselves
and the world. This would be no dogmatic assertion of atheism, but a claim that
allows the tiniest logical possibility that theism might be true. However, just
because something is logically possible is not, in itself, a reason to believe
it.
Perhaps the moral thing, the courageous
thing, is to adopt an agnosticism with strong atheist tendencies. Otherwise,
one might be open to the accusation of taking the easy way out. Pascal's Wager
is like this. You might as well believe in the existence of God, because, if
you are right, you gain an eternal reward; and, if you are wrong, you lose
nothing, since death is simply an end to conscious existence. On the other
hand, if you do not believe, and there is a God, woe betide you as a skeptic.
You have everything to lose and nothing to gain by your disbelief. Is
agnosticism is a similar kind of insurance policy? Does the agnostic take false
comfort from the thought that it is better not to deny God’s existence
absolutely, since a wrathful God might be less wrathful with an agnostic than
an atheist?
Assuming for the sake of argument that
the problem of evil, the failure of the metaphysical ‘proofs’ for God’s
existence, and the lack of empirical support, all make God’s existence most unlikely.
The agnostic fails to take this into account for the sake of a peaceful life.
Run-ins between believers and nonbelievers are anything but peaceful. To push
atheism in the face of believers is to ask for aggravation.
A critic may claim that this reticence
points to another problem with agnosticism. It makes the agnostic too tolerant
of religion as a whole, and too willing to give equal time to positions that do
not warrant it. This is like a Creationist arguing that 'Intelligent Design'
ought to be given equal time in our schools with evolutionary theory. If things
are set 99 percent in one way, and 1 percent in another, there is no reason to
give equal time to both. If we accept reason’s urging to reject superstition
and to explain things as best we can with our limited human understanding,
then, perhaps, the courageous thing is to be a practical atheist, while
remaining a theoretical agnostic. Practical agnostics, on this account, are
indeed somewhat cowardly.
No comments:
Post a Comment